Im off for a few days while I head over to
Amsterdam for Christmas. I will be back early in the New Year with hopefully some slightly more polished things to say about modus ponens failures, Dr. Evil and countable additivity, privileged access and narrow content, and, it being unavoidable in January and February, philosophical gossip. (Though I can’t promise that the gossip will be polished – I half think I should promise that it will not be.) Happy holidays all, and good luck to everyone going on
the job market!
Monthly Archives: December 2002
I was updating a few
I was updating a few links when I discovered
something I didnt really expect to find out during a regular webcrawl. If you crawl
on over to John
Hawthornes CV, and scroll not too far down, youll see that he has a paper
forthcoming in The Monist, co-authored
with me. This is very
exciting news, especially to me!
Despite the somewhat incredulous tone of the last
paragraph, I was more or less aware that the
paper was more or less likely to appear,
so it wasnt like I had a paper accepted at a journal with no knowledge of it
(and in fact I even have a draft
of the paper available) but it still wasnt exactly how I expected to get
confirmation of another publication. I wonder if news of its acceptance is official
enough to put on this years annual report?
In other co-authoring news, it looks likely that
the paper Andy Egan and I wrote on pranks
will be presented at the Symposium
on Theoretical and Applied Ethics at LSU next February. I think its my
duty to play this up for all its worth – its only fair that adding a few
jokes to a good idea for a paper that someone else (i.e. Andy) had gets me to
count as an ethicist. Im not sure why its fair, but
now that Im an Ethicist, I can just say that its fair and thats already got
some evidential weight.
Well, heres
something you dont see every day. The review in Notre Dame Philosophical
Reviews of Beyond
Rigidity takes Soames to task for not being Millian enough. Thats the kind
of thing that happens in any field when you stake out an extreme position early
on, any subsequent movement back towards the middle ground will be interpreted
as betrayal by someone 😉
Well, heres
something you dont see every day. The review in Notre Dame Philosophical
Reviews of Beyond
Rigidity takes Soames to task for not being Millian enough. Thats the kind
of thing that happens in any field when you stake out an extreme position early
on, any subsequent movement back towards the middle ground will be interpreted
as betrayal by someone 😉
There are about a million
There are about a
million other things I should be doing right now, so its probably time to say
something more about Dr. Evil. I
knew that deep down one of the reasons I disliked approaches to probability
based on principles of indifference was that they threatened to collapse the
important distinction between risk and uncertainty. What I hadnt realised,
until very recently, was Adams argument for his indifference principle involves
just such a collapse at one point.
First some
background. To my mind, what should have been a very important discovery in
early 20th century work on probability was that there is a
distinction between risk and uncertainty. Heres how Keynes introduces the
concept of uncertainty in an article from 1937 (The General Theory of Employment
Quarterly Journal of Economics).
By uncertain
knowledge, let me explain, I do not mean merely to distinguish what is known
for certain from what is only probable. The game of roulette is not subject, in
this sense, to uncertainty; nor is the prospect of a Victory bond being drawn.
Or, again, the expectation of life is only slightly uncertain. Even the weather
is only moderately uncertain. The sense in which I am using the term is that in
which the prospect of a European war is uncertain, or the price of copper and
the rate of interest twenty years hence, or the obsolescence of a new
invention, or the position of private wealth owners in the social system in
1970. About these matters there is no scientific basis on which the for any
calculable probability whatever. We simply do not know. Nevertheless, the
necessity for action and decision compels us as practical men to do our best to
overlook this awkward fact and to behave exactly as we should if we ha behind
us a good Benthamite calculation of a series of
prospective advantages and disadvantages, each multiplied by its appropriate
probability, waiting to be summed.
I think this is
all incredibly important, and any theory that ignores the distinction between
what is probable and what is genuinely uncertain is mistaken. Decisions based
on what is probable or improbable are grounded at least in well understood
principles about risk; decisions grounded in what is genuinely uncertain are
not. And Im inclined to think that any theory that says that an agents attitude
to some uncertain propositions can be expressed by a single probability function
does ignore the distinction. This is especially true for theories that say this
about ideal agents.
This is hardly an
original thought. It was the basis of Keyness theory of probability outlined
in his dissertation of 1909, which eventually became the Treatise on Probability of 1921. Keynes had the probability, which
for him was just rational credence, of an uncertain proposition be a
non-numerical value. Ramsey criticised this on the grounds that probability
values are meant to enter into computations, according to the theory we can add
and multiply them, for example, and we dont know how to add and multiply
non-numerical values. In my dissertation, I proposed that the theory that holds
that the credal states of a rational agent can be
represented by a set of probability functions rather than just a single
probability function could capture all of Keyness insights without being
vulnerable to Ramseys objection. This is not a new theory, it has been
discussed by Isaac Levi (Ignorance, Probability and Rational Choice 1982) Richard
Jeffrey (Bayesianism with a Human Face 1983), Bas
van Fraassen (Figures in a Probability Landscape
1990) and extensively by Peter Walley (Statistical Reasoning With Imprecise
Probabilities 1991), and in Walleys case theres
some connection drawn to Keyness work, so I still dont want to make any dramatic claims to originality.
We draw a
connection between Keyness theory and these new theories by identifying the
probability of a proposition p as a
function from members of S, the set
of probability functions that represents the credal
states of an ideal agent, to [0, 1], where the value of the function is
the value of P(p) according to each P in
S. For most purposes we can simplify
this by saying the probability of p
is the range of that function. Then p
has a numerical probability in Keyness sense iff its probability is a singleton,
it is uncertain otherwise. Arguably the range of the function should always be
an interval (well, I argue for this at any rate) and if so we can say p is more uncertain the larger that
interval is. This gives us a concept of comparative uncertainty, and with that
we can say that everything Keynes
says in the above quote is true.
Now one of the
surprising things about interpreting Keyness term uncertainty this way is
that a proposition can become more uncertain as we acquire more evidence about
it. Keynes seemed to think this was impossible, but here I think he was just
mistaken about the behaviour of some of his own concepts. (We all make
mistakes.) Heres a case where just that happens. (As it turns out, its a case
Ive written about. See my Keynes,
Uncertainty and Interest Rates Cambridge
Journal of Economics 2000).
Im watching a
roulette game going on, and in particular paying close attention to one player,
called Kim. Its a crowded room, so I cant see the roulette wheel, or the
board where bets are placed, but I can see the croupier, and I can see Kim. I see
Kim place a bet on either red or black (I can see that from where shes leaning
over the table) but I cant tell which. And I have no evidence that tells me
one way or the other. I know from prior observation that this is a fair
roulette wheel. And I can see that the croupier is about to spin the wheel. Now
consider the following propositions. (For simplicity well assume its a
roulette wheel with no green slots – this makes the example rather unrealistic,
but simplifies the computations no end without having any major philosophical
costs.)
kr = Kim bet on red
kb = Kim bet on black
br = The
ball lands on red
bb = The ball lands on black
h
= Kim is happy in a few seconds
At this stage, I
think I can assign numerical probabilities in the following cases:
1. P(h
| kr Ù br) = 1
2. P(h | kr Ù bb)
= 0
3. P(h | kb Ù bb)
= 1
4. P(h | kb Ù br) = 0
5. P(br | kr) = ½
6. P(bb | kr)
= ½
7. P(br | kb) = ½
8. P(bb | kb) = ½
Also note {kr, kb} and {br, bb} are partitions, and my credences reflect that (e.g. P(kr Ú kb) = 1.)
What I cant do is
assign a numerical probability to kr or to kb, they
are just uncertain. Perhaps theyre not so uncertain that their probability is
[0, 1] – thats what happens when a proposition is completely uncertain,
but they are uncertain to a degree.
Now I wait a few
seconds, and see that when the wheel stops, Kim is happy. So I update my
credences accordingly. What should my new credences be? Some may suggest that
my credences in br,
bb and bg should be unchanged, because I
have no new evidence that is relevant to their assessment. But this must be
false. For if it were true, I could do the following computations (11 and 12
are background, the new assumptions come in at 13 and 14).
11. P(br) = ½ from 5 and 7
12. P(bb) = ½ from 6 and 8
13. P(br | h) = ½ by assumption
14. P(bb | h) = ½
by assumption
15. P(kr | h) = P(kr Ù br | h)
by 2
16. P(kr Ù br | h) = P(br | h) by 4
17. P(kr | h) = ½ by 13, 15 and 16
18. P(kb | h) = ½
by identical reasoning to the last three lines
19. P(br | Øh) =
½ (since by 11 and 13 br
and h are independent)
20. P(bb | Øh) = ½ (since
by 12 and 14 bb and h are independent)
21. P(kr | Øh) =
½ (by equivalent reasoning to 15-17, with just the relevant appeals changed)
22. P(kr) = ½ by 17 and 21
And 22 is just
what we said we couldnt conclude, because we werent in a position to assign
numerical probabilities to kr and kb. So the
simple assumption that we shouldnt change our credences in br and bb when we learn h must
have been mistaken. What should happen is that after learning h, br and bb should go from being not at all uncertain to being rather
uncertain, in fact exactly as uncertain as kr and kb were (and I guess still are).
This is contentious,
but I think that the same thing is going on in Adams main argument. (I.e. its
contentious that its the same thing.) Here are the main examples again.
TOSS&DUPLICATION After Al goes
to sleep, researchers toss a coin that has a 10% chance of landing heads. Then
(regardless of the toss outcome) they duplicate Al. The next morning, Al and the duplicate
awaken in subjectively indistinguishable states.
Adam wants to
argue that in this case when Al wakes up his credence in HEADS should be 1/10.
A crucial premise in the argument for this is that P(HEADS/HeadsAl
or TailsDup) (TailsDup is
the proposition that hes the duplicate and the coin landed tails – you can
figure out the rest of the code from that) is also 1/10. And he argues for that
as follows.
COMA As in TOSS&DUPLICATE, the
experimenters toss a coin and duplicate Al. But the following morning, the
experimenters ensure that only one person wakes up: If the coin lands heads, they allow Al to wake up (and put the
duplicate into a coma); if the coin lands tails, they allow the duplicate to
wake up (and put Al into a coma)
Suppose that in the COMA case, Al
gets lucky: the coin lands heads, and so the experimenters allow him to awaken.
Upon awakening, Al is immediately in a position to assert Either I am Al and
the coin landed heads, or else I am the duplicate and the coin landed tails.
So when Al wakes up in the COMA case, he has just the evidence about the coin
toss as he would have if he had been awakened in TOSS&DUPLICATE and then been told [HeadsAl
or TailsDup]. So to defend (3)to show that in the
latter case Als credence in HEADS ought to be 10%it is enough to show that when
Al wakes up in the COMA case, his credence in HEADS ought to be 10%.9 Let me
argue for that claim now.
Before Al was put to sleep, he was
sure that the chance of the coin landing heads was 10%,
and his credence in HEADS should have accorded with this chance: it too should
have been 10%. When he wakes up, his epistemic situation with respect to the
coin is just the same as it was before he went to sleep. He has neither gained
nor lost information relevant to the toss outcome. So his degree of belief in
HEADS should continue to accord with the chance of HEADS at the time of the
toss. In other words, his degree of belief in HEADS should continue to be 10%.
Adam considers an
objection that Als memories should give him evidence that hes Al, and hence given
HeadsAl or TailsDup, he
should have a very high credence in HEADS. He responds as follows:
Thats all
wrong. TRUST YOUR MEMORIES, AL makes the same mistake that TRUST YOUR MEMORIES,
OLEARY does. While it is true that in the absence of defeating auxiliary
beliefs, one ought to trust ones memories, when Al wakes up he does have defeating auxiliary beliefs. He is sure thatwhatever
the outcome of the coin tosssomeone was to wake up in just the
subjective state he is currently in. As far the outcome of the coin toss goes,
the total evidence Al has when he wakes up warrants exactly the same opinions
as the total evidence he had when he went to sleep.
This is what I
think is wrong. Adam is concerned to reject the line of reasoning that memories
provide evidence, because he thinks that theyre really only q-memories and
they dont count for very much. But this ignores a crucial point I think. Al
doesnt know whether his memories are real memories or mere q-memories. But
Adam thinks that he can assign a very precise credence to their being real: in
this case exactly 1/10. I dont think this is true, and I think the only way
youd come to infer it is by more or less presupposing an indifference
principle.
Id put the
dialectic as follows. Al has some memories. These are actually conclusive
evidence that HEADS, though of course Al doesnt know this. In fact he has no
idea whatsoever what the evidential force of those memories is. But that doesnt
mean he should act as if they have no evidential value at all – if he does hes
drawing a substantive conclusion, that q-memories have no evidential value from
premises that are essentially worthless, that he has no idea how much
evidential worth they have. (Substantive and, we might as well note, false.) He
should act like he has no idea how valuable the evidence is, just like in the
casino case I should act like I have no idea what the evidential force of h is. In that case I go from regarding br as risky to
regarding it as uncertain. I think Als attitude towards HEADS should be the
same in COMA. And if it is, the argument for the indifference principle in the Dr. Evil
paper fails.
There are about a million
There are about a
million other things I should be doing right now, so its probably time to say
something more about Dr. Evil. I
knew that deep down one of the reasons I disliked approaches to probability
based on principles of indifference was that they threatened to collapse the
important distinction between risk and uncertainty. What I hadnt realised,
until very recently, was Adams argument for his indifference principle involves
just such a collapse at one point.
First some
background. To my mind, what should have been a very important discovery in
early 20th century work on probability was that there is a
distinction between risk and uncertainty. Heres how Keynes introduces the
concept of uncertainty in an article from 1937 (The General Theory of Employment
Quarterly Journal of Economics).
By uncertain
knowledge, let me explain, I do not mean merely to distinguish what is known
for certain from what is only probable. The game of roulette is not subject, in
this sense, to uncertainty; nor is the prospect of a Victory bond being drawn.
Or, again, the expectation of life is only slightly uncertain. Even the weather
is only moderately uncertain. The sense in which I am using the term is that in
which the prospect of a European war is uncertain, or the price of copper and
the rate of interest twenty years hence, or the obsolescence of a new
invention, or the position of private wealth owners in the social system in
1970. About these matters there is no scientific basis on which the for any
calculable probability whatever. We simply do not know. Nevertheless, the
necessity for action and decision compels us as practical men to do our best to
overlook this awkward fact and to behave exactly as we should if we ha behind
us a good Benthamite calculation of a series of
prospective advantages and disadvantages, each multiplied by its appropriate
probability, waiting to be summed.
I think this is
all incredibly important, and any theory that ignores the distinction between
what is probable and what is genuinely uncertain is mistaken. Decisions based
on what is probable or improbable are grounded at least in well understood
principles about risk; decisions grounded in what is genuinely uncertain are
not. And Im inclined to think that any theory that says that an agents attitude
to some uncertain propositions can be expressed by a single probability function
does ignore the distinction. This is especially true for theories that say this
about ideal agents.
This is hardly an
original thought. It was the basis of Keyness theory of probability outlined
in his dissertation of 1909, which eventually became the Treatise on Probability of 1921. Keynes had the probability, which
for him was just rational credence, of an uncertain proposition be a
non-numerical value. Ramsey criticised this on the grounds that probability
values are meant to enter into computations, according to the theory we can add
and multiply them, for example, and we dont know how to add and multiply
non-numerical values. In my dissertation, I proposed that the theory that holds
that the credal states of a rational agent can be
represented by a set of probability functions rather than just a single
probability function could capture all of Keyness insights without being
vulnerable to Ramseys objection. This is not a new theory, it has been
discussed by Isaac Levi (Ignorance, Probability and Rational Choice 1982) Richard
Jeffrey (Bayesianism with a Human Face 1983), Bas
van Fraassen (Figures in a Probability Landscape
1990) and extensively by Peter Walley (Statistical Reasoning With Imprecise
Probabilities 1991), and in Walleys case theres
some connection drawn to Keyness work, so I still dont want to make any dramatic claims to originality.
We draw a
connection between Keyness theory and these new theories by identifying the
probability of a proposition p as a
function from members of S, the set
of probability functions that represents the credal
states of an ideal agent, to [0, 1], where the value of the function is
the value of P(p) according to each P in
S. For most purposes we can simplify
this by saying the probability of p
is the range of that function. Then p
has a numerical probability in Keyness sense iff its probability is a singleton,
it is uncertain otherwise. Arguably the range of the function should always be
an interval (well, I argue for this at any rate) and if so we can say p is more uncertain the larger that
interval is. This gives us a concept of comparative uncertainty, and with that
we can say that everything Keynes
says in the above quote is true.
Now one of the
surprising things about interpreting Keyness term uncertainty this way is
that a proposition can become more uncertain as we acquire more evidence about
it. Keynes seemed to think this was impossible, but here I think he was just
mistaken about the behaviour of some of his own concepts. (We all make
mistakes.) Heres a case where just that happens. (As it turns out, its a case
Ive written about. See my Keynes,
Uncertainty and Interest Rates Cambridge
Journal of Economics 2000).
Im watching a
roulette game going on, and in particular paying close attention to one player,
called Kim. Its a crowded room, so I cant see the roulette wheel, or the
board where bets are placed, but I can see the croupier, and I can see Kim. I see
Kim place a bet on either red or black (I can see that from where shes leaning
over the table) but I cant tell which. And I have no evidence that tells me
one way or the other. I know from prior observation that this is a fair
roulette wheel. And I can see that the croupier is about to spin the wheel. Now
consider the following propositions. (For simplicity well assume its a
roulette wheel with no green slots – this makes the example rather unrealistic,
but simplifies the computations no end without having any major philosophical
costs.)
kr = Kim bet on red
kb = Kim bet on black
br = The
ball lands on red
bb = The ball lands on black
h
= Kim is happy in a few seconds
At this stage, I
think I can assign numerical probabilities in the following cases:
1. P(h
| kr Ù br) = 1
2. P(h | kr Ù bb)
= 0
3. P(h | kb Ù bb)
= 1
4. P(h | kb Ù br) = 0
5. P(br | kr) = ½
6. P(bb | kr)
= ½
7. P(br | kb) = ½
8. P(bb | kb) = ½
Also note {kr, kb} and {br, bb} are partitions, and my credences reflect that (e.g. P(kr Ú kb) = 1.)
What I cant do is
assign a numerical probability to kr or to kb, they
are just uncertain. Perhaps theyre not so uncertain that their probability is
[0, 1] – thats what happens when a proposition is completely uncertain,
but they are uncertain to a degree.
Now I wait a few
seconds, and see that when the wheel stops, Kim is happy. So I update my
credences accordingly. What should my new credences be? Some may suggest that
my credences in br,
bb and bg should be unchanged, because I
have no new evidence that is relevant to their assessment. But this must be
false. For if it were true, I could do the following computations (11 and 12
are background, the new assumptions come in at 13 and 14).
11. P(br) = ½ from 5 and 7
12. P(bb) = ½ from 6 and 8
13. P(br | h) = ½ by assumption
14. P(bb | h) = ½
by assumption
15. P(kr | h) = P(kr Ù br | h)
by 2
16. P(kr Ù br | h) = P(br | h) by 4
17. P(kr | h) = ½ by 13, 15 and 16
18. P(kb | h) = ½
by identical reasoning to the last three lines
19. P(br | Øh) =
½ (since by 11 and 13 br
and h are independent)
20. P(bb | Øh) = ½ (since
by 12 and 14 bb and h are independent)
21. P(kr | Øh) =
½ (by equivalent reasoning to 15-17, with just the relevant appeals changed)
22. P(kr) = ½ by 17 and 21
And 22 is just
what we said we couldnt conclude, because we werent in a position to assign
numerical probabilities to kr and kb. So the
simple assumption that we shouldnt change our credences in br and bb when we learn h must
have been mistaken. What should happen is that after learning h, br and bb should go from being not at all uncertain to being rather
uncertain, in fact exactly as uncertain as kr and kb were (and I guess still are).
This is contentious,
but I think that the same thing is going on in Adams main argument. (I.e. its
contentious that its the same thing.) Here are the main examples again.
TOSS&DUPLICATION After Al goes
to sleep, researchers toss a coin that has a 10% chance of landing heads. Then
(regardless of the toss outcome) they duplicate Al. The next morning, Al and the duplicate
awaken in subjectively indistinguishable states.
Adam wants to
argue that in this case when Al wakes up his credence in HEADS should be 1/10.
A crucial premise in the argument for this is that P(HEADS/HeadsAl
or TailsDup) (TailsDup is
the proposition that hes the duplicate and the coin landed tails – you can
figure out the rest of the code from that) is also 1/10. And he argues for that
as follows.
COMA As in TOSS&DUPLICATE, the
experimenters toss a coin and duplicate Al. But the following morning, the
experimenters ensure that only one person wakes up: If the coin lands heads, they allow Al to wake up (and put the
duplicate into a coma); if the coin lands tails, they allow the duplicate to
wake up (and put Al into a coma)
Suppose that in the COMA case, Al
gets lucky: the coin lands heads, and so the experimenters allow him to awaken.
Upon awakening, Al is immediately in a position to assert Either I am Al and
the coin landed heads, or else I am the duplicate and the coin landed tails.
So when Al wakes up in the COMA case, he has just the evidence about the coin
toss as he would have if he had been awakened in TOSS&DUPLICATE and then been told [HeadsAl
or TailsDup]. So to defend (3)to show that in the
latter case Als credence in HEADS ought to be 10%it is enough to show that when
Al wakes up in the COMA case, his credence in HEADS ought to be 10%.9 Let me
argue for that claim now.
Before Al was put to sleep, he was
sure that the chance of the coin landing heads was 10%,
and his credence in HEADS should have accorded with this chance: it too should
have been 10%. When he wakes up, his epistemic situation with respect to the
coin is just the same as it was before he went to sleep. He has neither gained
nor lost information relevant to the toss outcome. So his degree of belief in
HEADS should continue to accord with the chance of HEADS at the time of the
toss. In other words, his degree of belief in HEADS should continue to be 10%.
Adam considers an
objection that Als memories should give him evidence that hes Al, and hence given
HeadsAl or TailsDup, he
should have a very high credence in HEADS. He responds as follows:
Thats all
wrong. TRUST YOUR MEMORIES, AL makes the same mistake that TRUST YOUR MEMORIES,
OLEARY does. While it is true that in the absence of defeating auxiliary
beliefs, one ought to trust ones memories, when Al wakes up he does have defeating auxiliary beliefs. He is sure thatwhatever
the outcome of the coin tosssomeone was to wake up in just the
subjective state he is currently in. As far the outcome of the coin toss goes,
the total evidence Al has when he wakes up warrants exactly the same opinions
as the total evidence he had when he went to sleep.
This is what I
think is wrong. Adam is concerned to reject the line of reasoning that memories
provide evidence, because he thinks that theyre really only q-memories and
they dont count for very much. But this ignores a crucial point I think. Al
doesnt know whether his memories are real memories or mere q-memories. But
Adam thinks that he can assign a very precise credence to their being real: in
this case exactly 1/10. I dont think this is true, and I think the only way
youd come to infer it is by more or less presupposing an indifference
principle.
Id put the
dialectic as follows. Al has some memories. These are actually conclusive
evidence that HEADS, though of course Al doesnt know this. In fact he has no
idea whatsoever what the evidential force of those memories is. But that doesnt
mean he should act as if they have no evidential value at all – if he does hes
drawing a substantive conclusion, that q-memories have no evidential value from
premises that are essentially worthless, that he has no idea how much
evidential worth they have. (Substantive and, we might as well note, false.) He
should act like he has no idea how valuable the evidence is, just like in the
casino case I should act like I have no idea what the evidential force of h is. In that case I go from regarding br as risky to
regarding it as uncertain. I think Als attitude towards HEADS should be the
same in COMA. And if it is, the argument for the indifference principle in the Dr. Evil
paper fails.
Ive had a few complaints about the way
pictures work on the blog, so Ive deleted the posts
involving graphics. So from now on itll just have to be me talking. That might
not be a good thing, but well see.
In both my recent notes
In
both my recent notes on indifference principles, the comments on Nick Bostroms
computer simulation paper and Adam Elgas Dr Evil paper, Ive mentioned that
the proponents of these theories assume a theory of evidence that is
intuitively quite plausible, and may have been the mainstream view not long
ago, and may even be ultimately true, but which is not very popular among
philosophers of perception these days. I didnt think much followed from this,
save perhaps that those presupposing a theory that is widely viewed as being
hopelessly befuddled owe us an explanation as to why they are sticking with it.
And in this little endeavour I have been utterly unsuccessful. This could be
because my heart hasnt really been in it due to underlying internalist sympathies,
or because Im wrong that the indifferentists need to address this, or because
Im no good at convincing people of things, or because of any number of other
reasons. Suffice to say that in some circles, the idea that when we look at a
hand we have evidence of an epistemically different kind to a brain-in-a-vat
that is stimulated in the way our brains are when we look at a hand is not
viewed as being particular plausible.
When
in trouble in a case like this, call in the heavy hitters. Alex Byrne has a paper
forthcoming in Noûs in which he
argues that the sceptical
paradoxes are not really deep paradoxes. By this he means, in part, that
there isnt anything like a compelling argument for scepticism. And this is because
he thinks that the canonical arguments for scepticism turn out to rest on very
implausible premises on close inspection. One of those premises is that
perceptual evidence underdetermines what the external world is like: we could
have just this evidence and be dreaming (or a brain-in-a-vat, etc.). This,
Byrne thinks, can be shown to be false simply by carefully reflecting on the nature
of evidence. The whole paper is worth reading, but let me just extract a few
choice quotes.
The
known (evidence) proposition e has yet to be identified. [Byrne has just
argued that evidence should be propositional. The challenge is to determine
whether there is any candidate to be e that is compatible with
thorough-going external world scepticism.]The candidates may be divided into
two classes. The firstclass I consists of propositions about Ss sense-data,
ideas, impressions, phantasms or other queer entities allegedly given in
experience. The secondclass IIconsists of propositions about how things look
or (visually) appear to S (cf. the first paragraph of this section [not
excerpted here.]).
It
is quite doubtful that (trivial exceptions aside) any propositions in class I
are true, a fortiori known; they may accordingly be dismissed. This
would have sounded dogmatic as recently as the first half of the twentieth
century: it is only in the last fifty years or so that the deep flaws in what
used to be called the representative theory of perception have become
gradually visible. Admittedly, not everyone agrees that the theory rests on a
soggy bog of error: in one form or another, it still has its defenders. However,
it is unnecessary here to rehash the argument: because we are playing the first
sceptical game, the sceptic must steer clear of philosophical controversy.
That
leaves the members of class II: propositions about how things look or appear to
Sin other words, certain propositions about Ss mental states.
But because the representative theory of perception is off-limits, there is
very little motivation for thinking that ones knowledge of the external world
rests on a foundation of knowledge about ones own psychology
Propositions
about how things look or appear to S can be divided into two types. The
firsttype IIEcomprises external world propositions,
because they entail the existence of o: that o looks square to S,
that it appears to S that o is square, etc. Hence, propositions
of type IIE, despite not entailing p, and perhaps being
known by S, are quite unsuitable candidates to be e. For e is
not supposed to be an external world proposition.
The
secondtype IIIcomprises those propositions about how
things look or appear to S that are not external world propositions (or
so we may suppose): that it appears to S that (some x) x is
square, that it appears to S that the F is square (for various fillings
for F, e.g. tile, pink thing), etc. If e is to be found in
class II, it must be of type III.
[I]t
is not plausible that e is a type III proposition.
First, these propositions have to be true; clearly we need not suppose
that it appears to S that the tile, or the pink thing, is
square. But is it even clear that it must appears to S that (some x)
x is square? If not, then since there are no better candidates, e is
not a type III proposition. Second, S believes e, and it is
quite unobvious why S, if he is to know p via his senses, must
have any beliefs about how things appear, let alone believe one of the
specific propositions under consideration. Suppose S is a conceptually
challenged animal who cannot entertain these comparatively sophisticated
thoughts about appearances; does this fact alone imply that S cannot use
his eyes to come to know that o is square?
In both my recent notes
In
both my recent notes on indifference principles, the comments on Nick Bostroms
computer simulation paper and Adam Elgas Dr Evil paper, Ive mentioned that
the proponents of these theories assume a theory of evidence that is
intuitively quite plausible, and may have been the mainstream view not long
ago, and may even be ultimately true, but which is not very popular among
philosophers of perception these days. I didnt think much followed from this,
save perhaps that those presupposing a theory that is widely viewed as being
hopelessly befuddled owe us an explanation as to why they are sticking with it.
And in this little endeavour I have been utterly unsuccessful. This could be
because my heart hasnt really been in it due to underlying internalist sympathies,
or because Im wrong that the indifferentists need to address this, or because
Im no good at convincing people of things, or because of any number of other
reasons. Suffice to say that in some circles, the idea that when we look at a
hand we have evidence of an epistemically different kind to a brain-in-a-vat
that is stimulated in the way our brains are when we look at a hand is not
viewed as being particular plausible.
When
in trouble in a case like this, call in the heavy hitters. Alex Byrne has a paper
forthcoming in Noûs in which he
argues that the sceptical
paradoxes are not really deep paradoxes. By this he means, in part, that
there isnt anything like a compelling argument for scepticism. And this is because
he thinks that the canonical arguments for scepticism turn out to rest on very
implausible premises on close inspection. One of those premises is that
perceptual evidence underdetermines what the external world is like: we could
have just this evidence and be dreaming (or a brain-in-a-vat, etc.). This,
Byrne thinks, can be shown to be false simply by carefully reflecting on the nature
of evidence. The whole paper is worth reading, but let me just extract a few
choice quotes.
The
known (evidence) proposition e has yet to be identified. [Byrne has just
argued that evidence should be propositional. The challenge is to determine
whether there is any candidate to be e that is compatible with
thorough-going external world scepticism.]The candidates may be divided into
two classes. The firstclass I consists of propositions about Ss sense-data,
ideas, impressions, phantasms or other queer entities allegedly given in
experience. The secondclass IIconsists of propositions about how things look
or (visually) appear to S (cf. the first paragraph of this section [not
excerpted here.]).
It
is quite doubtful that (trivial exceptions aside) any propositions in class I
are true, a fortiori known; they may accordingly be dismissed. This
would have sounded dogmatic as recently as the first half of the twentieth
century: it is only in the last fifty years or so that the deep flaws in what
used to be called the representative theory of perception have become
gradually visible. Admittedly, not everyone agrees that the theory rests on a
soggy bog of error: in one form or another, it still has its defenders. However,
it is unnecessary here to rehash the argument: because we are playing the first
sceptical game, the sceptic must steer clear of philosophical controversy.
That
leaves the members of class II: propositions about how things look or appear to
Sin other words, certain propositions about Ss mental states.
But because the representative theory of perception is off-limits, there is
very little motivation for thinking that ones knowledge of the external world
rests on a foundation of knowledge about ones own psychology
Propositions
about how things look or appear to S can be divided into two types. The
firsttype IIEcomprises external world propositions,
because they entail the existence of o: that o looks square to S,
that it appears to S that o is square, etc. Hence, propositions
of type IIE, despite not entailing p, and perhaps being
known by S, are quite unsuitable candidates to be e. For e is
not supposed to be an external world proposition.
The
secondtype IIIcomprises those propositions about how
things look or appear to S that are not external world propositions (or
so we may suppose): that it appears to S that (some x) x is
square, that it appears to S that the F is square (for various fillings
for F, e.g. tile, pink thing), etc. If e is to be found in
class II, it must be of type III.
[I]t
is not plausible that e is a type III proposition.
First, these propositions have to be true; clearly we need not suppose
that it appears to S that the tile, or the pink thing, is
square. But is it even clear that it must appears to S that (some x)
x is square? If not, then since there are no better candidates, e is
not a type III proposition. Second, S believes e, and it is
quite unobvious why S, if he is to know p via his senses, must
have any beliefs about how things appear, let alone believe one of the
specific propositions under consideration. Suppose S is a conceptually
challenged animal who cannot entertain these comparatively sophisticated
thoughts about appearances; does this fact alone imply that S cannot use
his eyes to come to know that o is square?
Kieran Healy writes on the
Kieran
Healy writes on the (slow-)growing controversy over the role of intuitions
in philosophy. For background, see the papers by Jonathan Weinburg et
al here,
here
and here. (If you haven’t seen the survey results about intuitions on Gettier cases across cultural and social groups in these papers yet, you should. And prepare to be a little suprised.)
Kieran has a rather funny caricature of the way philosophers (or at least
metaphysicians) generally argue, but then goes off on a riff about why we
should care more about where intuitions come from.
In the meantime, you might be interested in looking at other writers, who
have explored the
idea that our intuitions might have institutional
roots; that culture might mold conceptions
of rationality and thus deeply affect
how you think; that classification
is a social process which might have its origins in
material life; and that although individual and social cognition interact in
complex ways, getting socialized into a culture often implies subscribing
to its point of view.
Im
not sure how any of this undercuts the use philosophers make of intuitions. It
seems to me that even if we acknowledge all of this, there are still epistemological
and metaphysical reasons to use intuitions in philosophy. (You
mean youll be defending philosophy by using more philosophy? Yeah,
well what did you expect me to use, chemistry or something?)
The
epistemological reason is that for each of these facts about intuition, we
could (I think) find an equally
disturbing fact about perception. How we see the world around us is affected by
the kind of culture were in, what we expect to find and so forth. But none of
that implies that we should stop trusting perceptions as a source of evidence,
provided were suitably careful about how we employ them. Of course, practically
nothing should stop us trusting perception as a source of
evidence; that way lies madness, if not philosophical
immortality.
The
metaphysical reason is that intuitions are sometimes constitutive of the
concepts were aiming to analyse. Want to know whats a house? Well, presumably
houses are things that satisfy the predicate house, or fall under the concept
HOUSE. And presumably the facts about what makes an object satisfy the
predicate house include facts about how the term house gets the meaning it
gets in the language we speak. And presumably those facts include facts about
the intuitions people have about houses. A similar story is probably true for
the concept HOUSE, though here there are some more prominent
dissenters. Now its rather controversial whether a similar story could be
true if we replaced house with item of knowledge, or rational belief, or mind,
or person, or just act, or (I guess most controversially) object, but at
least for terms towards the left of that list, it seems plausible enough.